Monday, December 24, 2012

The moral animal

A letter, to the NYTimes:


To the Editor;

Thanks are in order for Jonathan Sacks.  His insight ("The moral animal" December 24, 2012) can help us to celebrate the humanity in this season.

And yet, his comment, "Religion is the best antidote to the individualism of the consumer age"  demonstrates the irony of modern personal salvation. Spiritual evangelicals of all faiths, including that of reason, engage in an other-directed and community-minded action for the sake of the enlightened self-interest.  In this new age of accumulative theology, we consume belief in order to better our selves.



Friday, December 21, 2012

Sacrificing Head Start?

A federal study demonstrates that by the end of 3rd, students who had been enrolled in Head Start, have little to no advantage over students never enrolled: "Yasmina Vinci, the executive director of the National Head Start Association, called the vanishing impacts of Head Start in the early grades "troubling," but noted that Head Start does its core job well by preparing disadvantaged children for kindergarten. "Our work with students ends when children graduate from Head Start, but it is clear that for many, their circumstances continue to hinder their success; circumstances including, but not limited to, the quality of their primary and secondary education," she said in a prepared statement."

There are those will use this report to call for Head Start to be defunded, at the federal level.  A thought experiment.  Suppose they win this call, based on this study.  As a result, Head Start is completely defunded, on the argument that the $8b spent on these kids has no residual effect.

That would mean that Congress accepts the idea that the long-term effects of education may not and perhaps can not be known until several years afterward.  In other words, would using this evidence to impeach the impacts of the Head Start program be the same thing as claiming that standardized tests should not be used to evaluate a teacher and the school because the effects of that teacher can not be determined for several years?

Yes, Head Start would need be sacrificed, at least in the short term.  The statistics given in the new report express success in the students while they were enrolled (as Ms. Vinci notes).  Proponents of the program would not doubt point to those real effects in an effort not to shuttle the program.  However, the longitudinal advantage of having (mostly) Conservative education reforms accepting the irrelevance of real-time testing is humongous.

If progressive-minded educators and politicos have already hatched this plan, forgive me for spoiling the secret.

Thursday, December 13, 2012

The Fed's Contradiction or the WSJ's?

Today, I send the WSJ another letter.


To the Editors;

You attempt to ridicule the thinking of Fed Chairman Ben Bernanke "The economy needs more monetary stimulus because it is still too weak despite four years of previous and historic amounts of monetary stimulus." (The Fed's Contradiction, December 12, 2012).

And yet, you harbor similar reasoning for continuing the tax rates of the Bush era.  The economy needs lower tax rates because it is still too weak despite twelve years of previous and historic amounts of tax reduction.

You end the piece with this warning: "The bill for unbridled government spending stimulus is already coming due. Sooner or later the bill for open-ended monetary stimulus will arrive too."

You could have equally written that the bill for unbridled government tax cutting is already coming due.  Sooner or later the bill for open-ended tax cuts will arrive too.

Monday, December 10, 2012

Fiscal cliff and education

Rick Hess hides several pertinent points in his appeal to how to handle the 'fiscal cliff': "Look, let's keep this simple. As a nation, we're spending vast sums we don't have. In every year of President Obama's first term, we borrowed more than $1 trillion. Today, the federal debt stands at $16.4 trillion (we spend $220 billion a year just paying interest on the debt.) If we extend the Bush tax cuts, once again prolong unfunded "patches" to avoid pain associated with the alternative minimum tax and Medicare physician payments, and fail to make the cuts dictated by sequestration, the debt is expected to rise to more than $22 trillion by 2020. (I'm okay with going over the dreaded "fiscal cliff," even though the tax increases and spending cuts are expected to trim next year's GDP growth by a half-point, largely because doing so would cut that projected debt down to only $14 trillion in 2020.) Who's to blame? All of us. We're enjoying services that we don't want to pay for--which means we borrow the money, then leave the bill for our kids (that's right, to the same children we claim to love so much). Our profligacy is not just an economic concern; it's a vast, disheartening moral failing on our part."

'We' do not have the funds because we have disastrously reduced tax revenue aggressively since the 1980s.

'We' enjoy services that 'we' don't want to pay for only when those who use the services are distinct from those who pay for them.  With the increasing economic inequality society has experienced for the past generation, the haves (who do not need nor use these services) have more political power than the have nots (who, through wage stagnation; failure to reap benefits of productivity gains - going to profit rather than compensation; benefit loss through the de-unionization of workers).  As long as this continues, those on top will rebel against spending for those on the bottom. The more they feel they deserve their success, the more they will assume the rest of society deserves their failures.

'Our' profligacy is a 'moral failure' precisely because economic and political considerations pay attention only to the current economic status of the wealthy.  If a more conservative disposition were adopted, 'we' would recognize that our institutions are crumbling not because of economic and moral profligacy, but from a single-minded greed that forgets the role of society in individual thriving.

Hess adds later: " The solution is pretty straightforward. We need to get less and to pay more. When it comes down to it, there are only three real choices: raise taxes on folks besides the top two percent of households; reduce growth in the giant entitlement programs (Social Security, Medicare, and Medicaid); or cut other domestic programs. That's it. And given that most mandatory government spending now involves assistance for seniors, tackling Social Security and Medicare has to be a big piece of this."

Choice 1: raise taxes on everyone.  Exactly, though this need not be income taxes. Carbon (among other Pigouvian taxes) and trade transaction fees (among other forms of a Tobin tax) would also raise substantial revenue.  VAT and consumption taxes do fall regressively on the poor, though relief could come from lower their income or payroll tax deductions.

Choice 2 and 3 make sense only from the prospective of one not interested in admitting that a generation has seen wealth flow to the top <2 b="b">. As a smaller segment of the population has reaped enormous gains from the restructuring of the political and economy systems (see this book and this one and this one), that segment has willfully blinded itself to the effects on the overall society. Time to return to reinvest in the institutions, by reversing the gains.  This is not Marxism, Socialism, nor a resentment politics.  It is fairness and the conservative recognition that the economic changes of the past generation have not helped us but burdened us.





College accountability?

Kevin Carey, in the NYTimes, makes another case for standardizing college academic standards: "The lack of meaningful academic standards in higher education drags down the entire system. Grade inflation, even (or especially) at the most elite institutions, is rampant. A landmark book published last year, “Academically Adrift,” found that many students at traditional colleges showed no improvement in critical thinking, complex reasoning and writing, and spent their time socializing, working or wasting time instead of studying. (And that’s not even considering the problem of low graduation rates.)"

The use of the book Academically adrift is problematic for two reasons, both speculative (on my part, based on their data).  First, the number of students not having learned much of value in the author's most recent research equals the number of students more that attended college than the comparison year (2010 v. 1970).  In other words, the same number of students are learning now as their were students before (the total number of students v. a percentage of students).  Alone, that statistic could mean that for over a generation, we have been sending students to college that lack the basic qualifications to be there.  It would make sense that schools lowered the expectations in order to accommodate this influx.

Second, there are no meaningful measures of what percentage of students were learning things of value (or their level of effort) back in the earlier years.  Do the groups being compared merit comparison?  We do not know.  Without knowing a similar set of statistics, the socio-economic context from which these students attended college, the comparison between 2010 and 1970 is moot.

Carey offers a remedy to what he perceives as a problem: "But the most promising solution would be to replace the anachronistic credit hour with common standards for what college students actually need to know and to be able to do. There are many routes to doing this. In the arts and sciences, scholarly associations could define and update what it means to be proficient in a field. So could professional organizations and employers in vocational and technical fields."

Proficiency is the solution to avoid making college degrees "ultimately worthless."  His idea shares the foundational theory of the Bologna Process in Europe.  If all universities aligned in their outcome expectations of skills, knowledge and performance, then comparisons between graduates (for graduate schools and employment, among others) would be much easier.  A standard of what a college degree means, regardless of the college, would provide a clear, objective understanding to the students' degrees.

Learning is not a commodity, a consumable capable of being measured by quantity. No matter how well we formulate what a degree (or major) means, what the student learned and can later apply is a different question, one without a method of standardization, much less objective, empirical and quantitative meaning.  The purpose of higher education should be questioned, and its expense justified. But aiming for a single set of responses is folly, for the set of hoped for proficiencies are never-ending; who gets to decide what a graduate should know?  Better, from the democratic perspective, who is better able to determine what their graduates should know and do but colleges themselves, their faculty, board of trustees and alumni?

Standards of proficiency come from cost-benefit analyses of investing in education. Fair enough, just not sensible enough for an education that has meaning.

Thursday, December 6, 2012

Best interests and all that

Forget that Rick Santorum is a dingbat.  Look, instead, at what he considers dangerous in the recently defeated (by the US Senate) UN disabilities treaty, Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (CRPD): "Another example of this U.N. overreach is the treaty’s “best interests of the child” standard, which states in full: “In all actions concerning children with disabilities, the best interests of the child shall be a primary consideration.” This provision is lifted from the U.N. Convention on the Rights of the Child, which was also not ratified by the United States Senate. This would put the state, under the direction of the U.N., in the position of determining what is in the best interest of a disabled child, replacing the parents who have that power under current U.S. law."

I put that one section in bold to make reference to education.  Is not this exactly what we hear from politicking candidates and school leaders, intent on pushing through one version of school reform or policy over another?  The 'best interests of the child' standard frames the dialogue in favor of whoever makes that claim.  It is a challenge to the other side to demonstrate why your point of view is valid without having to provide the same kind of validity for those making the claim.  They position challengers to established policies or reform agenda as acting not in the child's best interest, simply because the challengers challenge the favored policy.  It act as a trump card, silencing not just dissent but productive, democratic dialogue.

Yet here, the Senate is specifically rejecting a treaty (based on US policy, our ADA and IDEA laws) because of this claim.  Because  the treaty establishes policy in the best interests of the child, the Senate (and its share of fellow traveler dingbats) worries that parents will lose control over their children.  Bureaucracy replaces parental discretion (in parentis loco, without the parents being loco). Therefore, the treaty dies.

OK.  So why, then, do policies in education get normed as being for the best interests of the child?  Why does that claim so effectively marginalize opposition, defame its challengers and norm the status quo or the interests of the reformers who wield this claim as a kind of negating QED?

Education is not about the best interests of the child.  It is done in the best interests of society.  Of course, no conservative would accept such a socialized, communitarian approach to education.  Focusing on the empowerment and personal gain of individual capacity fits more securely into the right-ish version of governmental intervention into our lives.  Schools must be for the benefit of the individual, because 'society,' as Margaret Thatcher liked to say, does not exist.

Now, though, the Senate has placed itself into contradiction:

  • Policy must be for the best interest of the child (education) because society is a phantom; maximizing liberty and personal responsibility are on the conservative agenda.
  • Policy must not be in the best interests of the child (human rights) because doing so would erect a totalizing bureaucracy that would triumph parental rights.

The issue here is less actual policy and more the process by which policy get enacted.  Ideology blinds to contingency.  Rhetoric works, only to the point where it gets challenged.  Meaning has its context; when it comes to determining what is to be done, be circumspect to the assumptions of each side.  When it comes to education, remember in whose interests the best interests of the child serve.


Wednesday, December 5, 2012

Cities and Schools

In a piece having nothing to do with education, Guardian essayist Richard Sennett closes with this: "We want cities that work well enough, but are open to the shifts, uncertainties, and mess which are real life."

Let me appropriate and translate his point about 'smart cities' in relation to schools.  Planned, efficient and effective classrooms will no doubt produce the learnings sought out in the objectives, goals, outcomes aims specified in the plans.  They can work, efficiently and with stream-lined focus, to generate the learning gains predicated by the plans, and expected as part and parcel of various forms of standards-based accountability.

What they lack, however, is the human dimension that makes the learning meaningful.  What Sennett calls 'the shifts, uncertainties and mess which are real life' can be experienced in schools as the spontaneous and originality of student insight, the unpredictable sense and meaning a student makes out of the lesson, the divergency of high level critical thought that evaluates rather than the rote, basal level of knowledge repetition (which demonstrates not much).

Transformative, lasting learning depends on a fair bit of trial and waste, respect for the unknown and unknowable and a searching kind of personal reflection and group empathy that can not be predicative of the lesson beforehand.  Smart classrooms, or those planned to the second with stable metrics of the learning, are not science; they are technology, the application of discovery and inquiry.  But that technology quickly engulfs the science and inquiry; discovery suffers for the sake of replication; inquiry for the sake of explicit outcomes.

"Well enough" is the killer point.  The question of what is well enough has become the political one, rendered into the practical one by the failure of school leaders (both administration and teachers, and unions) to articulate the false promise of what Sennett rightfully calls "Fordist" - the belief that all parts of learning are products that respond to and are enhanced through completely systemization.  Learning, the personal meaning and significance that education has for an individual, can be neither routinized nor  manufactured the way consumables are.

David Warlick, at smartblog/education, connects to education: "Formal education is a system that is comfortably predictable, shaped by institutional rules and easily gamed by people who like predictability and the security of rules. Sadly, as success in this world depends increasingly on inventive resourcefulness and a lifestyle of active continual learning, formal education has become more reliant on rigid standards-based instruction and a punitive reward system."

He seems to distinguish the school-based 'formal education' from 'authentic real world learning.'  What students learn to do in schools, confirmed and reinforced by the one-dimensional data collection that counts for evaluation, is to do school. The learn to school.  As long as learning to school matters more than learning to live in a plural, uncertain world, our society will increasing lack the skills to navigate the 'shifts, uncertainties and mess which are real life.'

Monday, December 3, 2012

Go further

Rick Hess makes a reasonable point: "Imagining you can use an interesting and novel (if overhyped) domestic grant program as the foundation for revamping foreign aid is peculiar."

He fails to explain why.  And that blinds him to a relevant question: Why is an interesting and novel (if overhyped, and not that novel) domestic grant program as the foundation for revamping domestic aid not peculiar?  Why would something that would not work on foreign purposes work for domestic purposes?

He adds another sharp insight: "I'm kind of surprised to learn that the Pulitzer Prize-winning Friedman believes our biggest failure in Middle East diplomacy has been not talking with Hamas about proficiency rates."

He fails to turn this reflection into an interesting question: Why is not talking about proficiency rates not our biggest failure in education?  Or, if you prefer to cancel out the double negatives, why is talking about proficiency rates part and parcel of our biggest failure in education?


Lastly, Hess writes: "And, the frustrating thing, is that for things like teacher evaluation and school turnarounds, how you do them matters a lot more than whether you do them." Go further, Rick and tell us who "you" are (is?).  If the doers are the teachers themselves, the practitioners in and of the field, that will result in a much different process and outcome than if "you" is reformers motivated by interests distinct from those of the teachers and learners.



Risk and waste

Bill Keller, in the NYTimes, makes an interesting point (about diplomacy and journalism) that corresponds smartly with teaching.  He writies, "In the end, you have to trust trained, experienced correspondents to judge how much risk is too much. And that brings me to the main point. To my mind, the bigger question for our business is not whether we sometimes err on the side of caution, but whether we are hiring, developing and deploying the next generation of trained, experienced correspondents to make those calls. That also happens to be the best possible investment in security."

To paraphrase and tweak to fit teaching,

  • Think of 'risk' as the cost of teacher professionalism. The question is whether we are inducting enough prudence and creativity in our newer teachers to give them the freedom and respect to develop the experience in order to effectively and responsibility to judge wisely what works for their students.  
  • Think of 'risk' as waste; society's willingness to let go the restrictive adherence to false consciousness of cost-benefit allowance of education spending.  Put another way, teaching is about taking chances; taking chances can be costly; the costs are the chances for students to learn in ways that resonate beyond the end of course assessments.

Distrust is much easier to generate than trust. Loss anxiety, and thus avoidance of risk, is much more aligned with the human condition than erring on the side of potential, and thus taking on more risk.  We seem to have given up on potential and settled for the simple, certainty of formulaic interventions in social action: financial engineering products; medical practice as a flow-chart of 'if/then' prognosis and diagnoses; plea-bargaining in the judicial system to avoid both reality and the expense of its pursuit; standardized curricula, lessons and their evaluations.

Keller recognizes that an induction process for newcomers to a field must rely more on the sagacity of the current practitioners more than the ideals of outside interests intent of reforming the field.  Yes; there is always the risk of hermetic insulation, a protective layer of reflexive rejection out of fear of losing autonomy.  That risk is not inevitable, assuming that those inside a profession develop the reflective, inquiry stance needed for ongoing development.  But fear of risk, erring on the side of caution, avoiding the public reaction to waste and excessiveness leads to and emerge from that closed-minded, protective attitude.

The big question: how do teachers reclaim (stake out) the kind of respect needed to foster the entrepreneurial risk that flows from and into transformative education?




Thursday, November 29, 2012

Henninger and the WSJ (part 17, at least)

Daniel Henninger, of the WSJ, in a pitch perfect example of Foxification  of news: "In 2008's election, many Republicans and independents voted for Mr. Obama to put a final nail in the coffin of Justice O'Connor's racial anxieties. The millions of them who then cast votes against Mr. Obama in 2012 did so almost wholly because of the status of the economy after four years of his presidency. No matter. They lost in 2012 because they're "too white.""

Did non-Democrats vote for Obama in 2008 merely because he was Black?   It had nothing to do with his opposition, contempt for the GOP, Obama's promise and vision, and a willingness to believe that politics (and governing) could once again be sober, rational and bipartisan?

Did anti-Obama voters pick Romney because they trusted his vision of economics (which was what?) more than Obama, and not because Obama was Black?

Henninger wants to have it both ways.  Obama won in 2008 because he was Black, but being Black had nothing to do with votes against him in 2012.  People who voted for him in 2008 were irrational; people who voted against him in 2012 were rational.

He also claims that, "When George W. Bush attracted 40% of the Hispanic vote in 2004, there was no cry that the Republican Party was "too white." The GOP's problem with Hispanics today is a tangle of issues involving the law, labor and assimilation that is hardly reducible to the accusation that the party is too white."

Except that being 'White' correlates highly with feeling threatened by the Brown-ing of America.  Hispanics voted for Bush 2 because of his immigration policies; Hispanics voted against Romney because, also, of his immigration policies.  True, but Romney's policies were driven by the fearful politics of White privilege and xenophobia, inflamed by red state news' (et. al.) reporting that the "Browns" are stealing jobs of "Whites," flooding the public services and thus raising the taxes of "Whites" and the leading cause of crime and violence in otherwise calm and peaceful "White" society.

Henninger and friends are free to believe what they want and to pitch false consciousness onto their readership.  That does not mean its readership needs to trust them.

Monday, November 26, 2012

Intellectual Empathy

Matthew Lee Anderson has the right idea: "The real problem seems to be that people are uncertain about what to do with our disagreements, how to open and conduct conversations across the aisle without sacrificing our core convictions ... And if the “first things” of our framework are really at stake, then it can be easy to slip into a belligerent defense rather than entering into open inquiry ... "

His solution seems spot on: "One way to cultivate such common ground in our own local communities is through what some of called “intellectual empathy,” or the decision to enter into a person’s way of the seeing the world and look along with them ...  Intellectual empathy is a form of seeing how.  As in, “Oh, I see how you could think that.  It’s wrong, but I can see how it might make sense.”  It is an act that is aimed, first and foremost, toward the good of understanding, a good that persuasion may flow from but can never precede."

Intellectual empathy, then, requires one person to accept that the other has legitimate reasons for her beliefs, regardless of the validity the one gives to them.  Giving reason, as Donald Schon described it, is the act of taking the position of the other, and recognizing that, just as each of us has (mostly) strong reasons for what we think and why we act as we do, so do others.  To deny them that level of reasonableness dehumanizes; a signaling, perhaps, more to our fear of making vulnerable our ideas and beliefs.

Moreover, intellectual empathy means embracing the other's view as one's own.  Until we get inside their thinking (by a process that helps us towards understanding the context and contingency of their view, the identity claims presented in their view, the normative and subjectivities involved in coming to their view), we will continue to treat their views as static and concrete, ignorant or uneducated, rather than stochastic, fluid and dependent on an overall world view and experience of living in the world view.

Problems arise when the one person implicitly devalues the other's opinions, thereby defaming her reasoning.  While one can see the other as mistaken or lacking in understanding, missing some key fact or factor or just poor in analytical ability, that is a second order understanding.  The first takes seriously that the other has reason for their understanding, and attempts to justify those reasons as reasonable.


Monday, November 19, 2012

Evolution and the Creationismists

Adam Laats, in an essay online at Chronicle of Higher Ed, writes this helpful description:
"As it stands, scientists' blundering hostility toward creationism actually encourages creationist belief. By offering a stark division between religious faith and scientific belief, evolutionary scientists have pushed creationists away from embracing evolutionary ideas. And, by assuming that only ignorance could explain creationist beliefs, scientists have unwittingly fostered bitter resentment among the creationists, the very people with whom they should be hoping to connect."

This paragraph gains traction by highlighting the dichotomous thinking involved between evolution and creationism. For one to to be valid, the other must be invalid. Truth is a kind of mercantilism reality, an either/or confrontation with what is.  Except, in this case, that very dichotomy is the problem.

One of the stronger arguments against teaching Creationism (or its variants, like I.D.) in science classrooms is that Creationism is not scientific.  Evolution is.  Creationism could be a topic in a Social Studies class, even a literature class. Not science because ... it is not scientific.  Making the choice one of either believing in Creationism or believing in evolution obviates that strength.  It all but forces a science teacher to incorporate Creationism into the curriculum; the dichotomy needs to be resolved.  Science v. Creationism.

For the moment, ignore the implications of believing one or the other.  Creationism, then, could be understood as a cosmology, not the process after cosmogenics.  Evolution, on the other hand, could be understood as the process after cosmogenics, not a theory of cosmology.  One narrates the beginning; the other, what happens next.   While I do not find much credence in Creationism, I can not impeach the theory.  It is un-impeachable, another trait that removes it from the scientific.  While I can not prove evolution, I can attempt to impeach it (in theory I could, had I enough background and methodology), its virtue of being scientific.

Laats makes a good point about taking seriously the reasoning behind those who back Creationism.  But because the belief is not science, and thus not open to rebuke, Creationismists should never be engaged in a battle of right v. wrong.  As Stephen Jay Gould wrote, treating them as "non-overlapping magesteria" is not a abdication of either.  It is, rather, a recognition that they are non-comparable.

Sunday, January 1, 2012

NYTimes, 1.1.12

Two articles that inspire thinking.

1.)  Sam Dillon covers the merit-pay system in the DC schools, originally created by Michelle Rhee and agreed to by the city's teachers' union.  This section, in particular, is worth commentary:
"Several respected studies have found that such payments have scant effect on student achievement; since most good teachers already work hard, before and after class, there are limits to how much more can be coaxed out of them with financial incentives ... But Washington is the leader among a handful of large cities that are seeking a more fundamental overhaul of teacher pay. Alongside the aggressive new evaluation system that has made the city famous for firing poor-performing teachers — more than 400 over the past two years — is a bonus-and-raise structure aimed at luring talented people to the profession and persuading the most effective to stick with it ... “The most important role for incentives is in shaping who enters the teaching profession and who stays,” said Eric A. Hanushek, a professor of economics at the Hoover Institution at Stanford University. “Washington’s incentive system will attract talented teachers, and it’ll help keep the best ones.”"

How does this system resemble the bonus culture in the financial industry, that rewards short-term profits while ignoring or failing to account for longer term failures?  Maximizing the short term often means not paying attention to whether those gains are solid and stable, robust and actual.  In education, just as in finance, whether the effects of policies aimed at short-term performance on learning tasks (like a focus on quarterly reported earnings) and the singular, aggressive use of standardized testing (like mortgage writing that pays little heed to the ability of the borrower to continually pay for their new home), merit-pay bonus culture in education narrows accounting to a series of metrics that report a snap-shot of student performance.  If a child or a group of children do well on these metrics, the teacher earns the reward.  What tells us, though, that such performance has any lasting significance?

It can be argued that long-term accounting on learning is impossible, since too many variables intercede, that time brings history and maturation which renders analysis on previous learning performance somewhat moot.  That, at best, we can measure and assume that our measurements are 'real' enough to base an evaluation of 'what has been learned.'  Or that incentives to think long-term are a virtual impossibility today, for industry at least (this article has an awesome quote on this: "Charles Holliday Jr., the C.E.O. of DuPont who retired three years ago, told me that it’s tough to get investors to think more than two years ahead — at most. “The stock market pays you for what you can do now,” he said.").

Fair enough.  But that does not obviate the need to understand why we want students to learn anything, or what it means to put to use that learning.  Put another way, do we even want to consider its usage, or just a documentation that something has at one time or another been learned, as measured in some way?

Further, does adopting a bonus culture make students the means towards a teacher's ends: their scores have value to the extent that they help teachers increase their salaries?  In other words, what are the ethics and morality (in a Kantian and a common sense way) of learning and treating students as autonomous rather than a method for accentuating adult compensation?  Pay attention to any critic of teachers, who argues that the unions are corrupt because they put the interests of the adults over that of children.  If they advocate merit pay performance practices, do they not do that as well?

*

2.) Geoffrey Wheatcroft writes about 'unknown knowns' on the Opinion page:
"He reminds us of the famous if gnomic saying by Donald H. Rumsfeld, then the United States secretary of defense, that “There are known knowns... there are known unknowns ... there are also unknown unknowns.” But the Irish problem, says Mr. O’Toole, was none of the above. It was “unknown knowns” ... What he means is something different from denial, or evasion, irrational exuberance or excess optimism. Unknown knowns were things that were not at all inevitable, and were easily knowable, or indeed known, but which people chose to “unknow”"

The fallacy Mr. Wheatcroft makes shows up a bit later: "The answer to that was obvious and could have been known to all, but too many people chose to unknow it."  Nothing is obvious.  Or rather, the obvious emerges in retrospection, once the full extent of circumstances, history and action can be grasped.  To believe otherwise is to embrace an idea of objective rationality, beloved by Plato, that one can emancipate themselves from ignorance by stepping out into the clear light of the Good.  It is to ignore the very real ways our minds are shaped by the contingent, the biased sifting of reality around us according to what we already know, already want and already have grasped.  It plays down human blindness, self-deception, motivated reasoning and the multiple forms of cognitive blindness that human thinking contains.  It makes a political comment - that some truths are desired in advance and history is somewhat inevitable based on what we know at any particular time.  It surrenders the concept of natality (from Arendt), of the radical emergence of possibility, unknowable in advance, that comes with free human action.

Truth is a narrative, an ongoing story that we understand in dynamic tension to the other stories we constantly live out.  To believe that something is obvious in the moment is how we experience life, yet requires almost exactly the kind of inventive ignoring that later perspectives will show as inherently partially and, well, unknowable; consciousness is conscious of something and, at least on the level of self-awareness, that something is circumscribed by our past experience and the limited nature of working and long-term memory.  We literally can not know everything; obviousness begets omniscience.  We are not our gods.

It would be different if Mr. Wheatcroft were simply saying, "I and others told you so." That is a fair description of what usually happens in debates, especially potent political dialogue and action.  And the current system of civil engagement and participation certainly does not harbor much respect for that kind of deeply intellectual, scientific, reasoned and disciplined kind of thinking.  Put another way, why a point of view carries the day matters not so much about what is real than it does about what narrative attracts the most support, support garnered through processes less adherent to truth and the obvious than to self-interested and contingent factors.  We are not fools, nor immoral for believing one thing over the other.  We do risk all kinds of fallacies and damage by not examining what we believe, why we believe it and ultimately what the consequences are of acting on that belief.